Calvinists Do Err: Superimposing Compatibilism & Determinism upon Extensivism


Paul Helm demonstrates an error common among Calvinists, which is to evaluate the cogency of Extensivist’s understanding of God’s salvation plan that includes man being endowed with libertarian freedom through the grid that compatibilism is prima facie true.[1] Rather than evaluating whether Extensivism provides a comprehensive, coherent, and biblically consistent perspective.

In contrast, one of my major objections to Calvinism is that I believe they fail to write, speak, pray or preach consistent with their chosen perspective of compatibilism and decretive theology. Of course they reject libertarian freedom as I reject compatibilism, but we should be able to evaluate each other’s perspective without superimposing the very idea the other perspective rejects as the only test of cogency. I do argue that their perspective is biblically wrong, but when I focus my evaluation on their commitment to compatibilism and decretal theology, I seek to do so through the lens of compatibilism and decretal theology rather than libertarianism.

Helm argues that libertarian freedom leaves saving grace to be merely the “action of God that is causally necessary, but never causally sufficient, for human salvation. For in the incompatibilist view of freedom what must, in addition, be causally necessary for receiving God’s grace is a free, incompatibilist choice. Divine grace and such a choice are then together causally sufficient for faith in Christ such a will has the power to resist or frustrate such grace from God. And given that humankind has a nature that is antipathetic to the rule of grace, we might expect such power to be exercised in the rejection of the overtures of grace. God’s saving grace is always resistible, and so saving grace can never ensure its intended effect[2] (italics added).

Note that this is another example of Calvinism’s attack on otherwise choice, demonstrating once again that all their talk of God’s salvific love for the non-elect, or their being genuinely offered salvation in the gospel is reduced to a hollow palliation for the crushing weight of compatibilism and unconditional election. Further, it makes all of their use of libertarian language all the more objectionable. Additionally telling is that he seems to equate determinism, (God’s monergistic unconditional election which predetermines the elect) with grace. That is to say, determinism is grace and grace is determinism; therefore, any concept such as otherwise choice that is not unilaterally and singularly deterministic cannot be comprehended in grace. Of course, such definitional exclusions emanate from Calvinism and not from Scripture or even logic.

Helm places salvational grace in one category and libertarian choice in another by the phrase “in addition,” as though choice is not, more to the point cannot, be a grace-enabled but undetermined component of God’s salvation plan. This leads to the obvious conclusion that faith, thusly categorized, emanates not from God’s gracious creative/redemptive plan but from man alone; it is thereby reduced to nothing more than an external contributor to grace human work. Such misunderstandings germinate many errors in Calvinism’s understanding of Extensivism.

To correct his misunderstanding let me say precisely, Extensivists believe that the salvific action of God is both causally necessary and causally sufficient, but it is not causally determinative. Moreover, we believe the action of God in grace was designed with two components in mind rather than just one, and both are equally of grace. Therefore, to propose that the “action of God” is only necessary but not sufficient is misrepresentative of Extensivism. It is an indefensible superimposition of compatibilism upon Extensivism.

I would mention that it does seem to be the ubiquitous teaching of Scripture that faith is necessary for salvation, and I would argue for regeneration as well. Even within Calvinism, most are adamant in their proclamation that a person is saved by faith. Now granted, the faith comes as a predetermined free act that is subsequent to monergistic quickening which cannot be resisted, and therefore completes salvation, but it is still essential for one to be deemed saved.

Consequently, the precise distinctions between the two perspectives is that the Calvinist faith is a determined free act of faith, and libertarian faith is an undetermined free act of faith. Additionally, Extensivists believe that faith initiates salvation, and in Calvinism, it is more accurate to say that it consummates salvation. Inextricably connected with this reality is the question of whether God freely chose to create man with otherwise choice and to restore such prior to actual salvation or not. If so, then grace is understood to restore the ability to choose in salvation, and it is not “in addition” to or instead of grace. Rather it is an integral component of the salvific grace plan of God.

Extensivism argues that Adam had choice due to creative grace. Subsequent to the fall, the restoration of choice in salvation is due to redemptive grace. That is to say, all that Adam had, including the ability to choose to follow God, was because God desired that for man and to be a part of his creation plan; therefore, choice was never something that arose merely from man, but rather creative grace bestowed on man in creation. Similarly, man’s ability to choose in salvation is not a work of man or something “in addition” to God’s grace, but rather it exist solely because God desired for that ability to be restored in his salvation plan of grace.

The grace-enablements that overcome the effects of the fall so that man may believe unto salvation do not eradicate or deliver an individual from all the effects of sin. They do not enlighten a person so that he can understand all that he might desire to know. Rather, they do sufficiently hold in abeyance the effects of the fall so that at the time of enlightenment and conviction, an individual may believe or resist the gospel, only now with greater knowledge, which is precisely what is seen in (John 12:35-36).

Helm’s assumption that compatibilism, with its exclusion of actual otherwise choice, is true, and that man being endowed with otherwise choice is not is quite understandable since he is a Calvinists and viewing those that disagree with him through the prism of compatibilism. What is not acceptable is his evaluation that libertarian freedom is found wanting because it does not measure up to some compatibly derived standard.

His proposed deficiency is not in libertarian freedom. For example, if we suppose that God created man with otherwise choice (denied in compatibilism), then it seems to follow that it is well within His power to restore such choice through grace-enablements, which seems to be precisely what we see depicted in Scripture. In view of that, we are back to the center of the issue, which is the nature of God and man.

Helm’s proposal seems to indicate that Calvinists must either believe that God is incapable of creating and governing man endowed with otherwise choice, as would be the case if God cannot foreknow actual contingencies (acts of libertarian free beings), as Calvinists and other determinists often argue. Or else, they simply believe He could have created such a world but did not.

The former is a view of God’s sovereignty, omnipotence, and omniscience that embraces the idea that God only knows what He foreordains, which is the view that I reject both biblically and logically. The latter option seems to mean that Extensivism is merely unfaithful to the beliefs of Calvinism, which is obviously and unabashedly true. This does nothing to undermine Extensivism’s biblical fidelity. Either option seems to posit the weakness in Calvinism. My comment here has nothing to do with Calvinists’ belief that Calvinism is true and Extensivism is not, but rather that they do not, or cannot, entertain the idea of Extensivism’s plausibility because they cannot disabuse themselves of compatible definitions and standards.

Furthermore, he equates one having the ability to resist the offer of salvation with being able to “frustrate” grace. Once again, he posits otherwise choice outside of God’s plan of salvation by grace, as though it is a competing rogue force outside of God’s sovereignty and against God’s grace plan. Admittedly, given the truth of compatibilism, it is impossible, given the same nature or past, for a person to choose at any time between accessible options regarding salvation.

However, given the truth of libertarianism, it is possible, given the same nature or past, for a person to choose between accessible options, not just regarding salvation, so long as such is within the range of options. Subsequent to the fall of man, I do not contend that man can act or think righteously, or make a spiritually restorative choice apart from God’s redemptive grace. Thus, the difference between the two positions is not necessarily the degree of depravity nor whether grace is sufficient to accomplish God’s goal, but rather it is found in the question of what is encompassed in God’s “intended effect” or goal of provisioning grace. What is included and excluded in God’s plan for the creation and redemption of man.

Calvinism asseverates that God’s salvific grace is to secure the salvation of the unconditionally elected while denying the same to the non-elect. All of which is accomplished within a compatibilist perspective. To even suggest the idea of God giving man a choice between accessible options within compatibilism is a twaddly distraction. In stark contrast, in Extensivism, God’s goal, “intended effect” of grace, is to provide salvation for everyone and secure it for those who exercise grace-enabled faith; accordingly, the exercise of faith is not “additional” or some sort of interloper into God’s grace salvation plan but a God-appointed essential component.

Now regarding his conclusion that if the offer of salvation is resistible, saving grace can never “ensure its intended effect.” I would say, that this statement is only true within a deterministic compatibilism because if compatibilism is true that means God created man without otherwise choice, and it then easily follows that regeneration is irresistible and monergistic.

Contrariwise, if the “intended effect” is to redeem man whom God created with otherwise choice, then it easily follows that salvation by grace includes the necessity of the person exercising grace enabled faith, while maintaining the simultaneous prerogative to resist being within the range of options during the offer of salvation; even though the person would most assuredly have greater knowledge about what he was rejecting than prior to being enlightened by the gospel (John 12:35-36). If one denies man’s creative or redemptive ability to reject God’s grace, then he is actually superimposing compatibilism upon libertarianism, the Calvinist error.

Therefore, what Helm has demonstrated is that a plan encompassing libertarian freedom is incompatible with salvation viewed through a compatibilist grid; to which I say of course. It does not accomplish the goal of Calvinist compatibilism, and that is the point. Instead the goal is and should be biblical fidelity.

A major difference between Calvinism and Extensivism is that grace operates one dimensionally in Calvinism. It comes determinatively upon the elect from God via unconditional election and selective regeneration. In contrast, within Extensivism, grace operates two dimensionally but still from only one source, which is God. The grace from Him provides everything for salvation, including the grace-enabled ability, at the moment of the gospel presentation, to be able to understand enough to exercise faith or turn and walk away. Both are acts of grace. It is true that man in sin can on his own resist God, but even this is only because God permits him to do so because if it were not for God’s plan of grace, man would instantly be annihilated. However, a sinner cannot reject the gospel with a full understanding of what he is rejecting without grace-enablement (Matthew 12:30-32; John 12:35-36).

If the ability to resist the gospel was not a part of God’s plan, no one would be able to walk away from a sovereign, omnipotent God. Thus grace in the libertarian view is causally sufficient for salvation when all aspects of the grace-salvation plan are present. A rejection of such places one in the camp of Calvinism, in which the call of the gospel is actually meaningless since neither the non-elect nor the elect (the latter prior to quickening) is capable of doing anything but rejecting the gospel; hence, deeply imbedded in the bowels of Calvinism, the gospel is not, in and of itself, good news. Rather, finding out you are on the unconditionally elect roster is the only good news.

Our evaluation of whether man is endowed with compatible or libertarian freedom should be determined from what we find in Scripture, rather than whether compatibilism is consistent with libertarian or libertarian is consistent with compatibilism, which is obviously not the case. As a system, I do not evaluate Calvinism by whether it is consistent with libertarian freedom, but rather whether it is consistent with its chosen perspective of compatibilism. Calvinists should do the same when evaluating Extensivism as a system. The biblical cogency of each perspective can only be fairly evaluated by properly describing the essence of the perspective and whether properly described, it is precisely reflective of Scripture.

The disallowance of otherwise choice in Calvinism, must always be as publicly obvious in their preaching, prayers, counseling, and writing as it is in their theological and philosophical rejection of such as being excluded by grace.

That is to say, be a compatibilist if you so choose, but be clear and consistent. Do not speak in ways that becloud that commitment by employing libertarian ideas that confuse the mutual exclusivity of the two perspectives.


[1] I use Extensivist as a general term for non-Calvinist.
[2] Paul Helm, “The Augustinian-Calvinist View” in Divine Foreknowledge, Four Views, edited by James K. Beilby and Paul R. Eddy (Carlisle, Cumbria, UK: Paternoster, 2001), 170.

Ronnie W. Rogers